Showing posts with label The Prestige. Show all posts
Showing posts with label The Prestige. Show all posts

Sunday, January 25, 2015

The Prestige and Metaphysics

Descartes shed all of his basic beliefs and senses to try and get rid of all things that were assumed. The Prestige relates to this concept in several ways.

The magicians need to see past the illusion they are being presented with. The magician's job is to fool the audience. Conversely, the magician also wants to see the illusions so that they may create their own. This parallels Descartes' desire to see past the veil of reality.

The magicians, more than wanting to distinguish illusion, want to know the truth of the act so that they may learn and repeat it. This desire to know the truth of reality is the goal of Descartes' meditation. Angier needed to know the reality so badly that he got Tesla to invent his own method of doing the transported man. But even then the only thing he wanted was to know how the rival magician did the trick. It truly displays the maddening desire and obsession to know the truth.

A moment of comparison is when the trick engineer says that he can't know how the way the transported man works, but we can do it with a double. Angier insists on doing it the way it was originally done. This parallels Descartes' idea that the senses cannot be trusted but that  he because a person thinks and realizes things they exist. The trick engineer knows that it will be impossible to figure it out without taking extreme measures. He is trusting in his own knowledge and experience. Angier is demanding his sense explain it to him.

The movie is all about people manipulating senses to fool someone's sense of reality. While it is more people manipulating than an all powerful being it almost validates Descartes' fear of the senses being fooled. Different magicians not only confuse reality for their audience but also break the illusion to sabotage each other.

The most significant evidence for the veil of reality is the cloning machine. This is by all means an incredible achievement and machine. But instead of simply displaying the wonder of the machine, he sets it up so it looks like a trick. This seems the most like a powerful being hiding reality from others. Because other magic tricks were theatrics or slights of hand to entertain. The machine was used to cause spontaneous biogenesis of a new person with the same identity. That is by any measure a god like power. But rather than presenting it as such Angier hides it behind a complex system to make sure nobody knows. This seems to completely follow Descartes' idea of a powerful being manipulating reality to fool everyone. Though Angier was clearly far from an all powerful being it is a great example of why it isn't a good idea to rely completely on the sense.

The Necessary Third: Magic, Miracles and Metaphysics

Over the last several years, I've written and thought quite a bit about a certain theory in robotics known as "the uncanny valley." My interest in this theory was initially inspired by Descartes' basic metaphysical concern: how do we know that what we are experiencing is "real"? On different occasions, I've employed the uncanny valley-- or, more accurately, my amended version of that theory-- to analyze a number of phenomena in our everyday experience, including our aversion to racial passing and the transgression of gender norms, (You can read my entire series of essays on the uncanny valley here.) Recently, I was hosting a couple of house guests, and one morning over coffee we had a conversation that re-sparked my uncanny valley curiosity. My guest described a project he was working on that dealt with mirror neurons and whether or not they were really the cause for the affective phenomenon we call "empathy." At any rate, in the course of describing our (and other animals') apparent ability to "experience" or "feel" things empathetically-- that is, without experiencing those things first-hand-- my interlocutor described the empathizer's experience as a kind of "simulation." That is, he speculated that when we feel (empathetic) pain upon witnessing another's injury, for example, what is happening is that our brain is neurologically "mirroring" the experience of the other, in effect manufacturing a simulation of that experience that convinces us, physically and emotionally, that we are experiencing the same injury.

Now, what I found interesting about this, and what led me back down the rabbit-hole of the uncanny valley, was that it again raised the fundamental question: is it possible to have the experience of a "perfect" simulation? The theory of the uncanny valley, of course, suggests that it is not possible. As least when it comes to simulations of the human form, the uncanny valley phenomenon seems to show that our brains are structured in such a way as to generate extreme aversion to, and ultimately to reject, simulations that too closely approximate the "real." In my earlier posts on the subject, I elaborated upon this further, speculating that this is because we are cognitively "hard-wired" to protect the distinction between reality and simulation, much in the same way that we need the distinction between "true" and "false," or between a proposition and its negation. Implicit in my earlier musings on this topic, but not quite explicated, was the suggestion that, although it may be (technologically) possible to manufacture something like a perfect simulation (in the sci-fi, "virtual reality" sense), it would be impossible to experience a perfect simulation qua "a perfect simulation." As I said earlier, if a simulation is perfect, then my experience of it will be indistinguishable from my experience of the "real" thing that it is simulating. Hence, any first-person phenomenological account I give of that experience will NOT be an account of a "simulation" but of (what I take to be, albeit mistakenly) an experience of the "real."

This is why, I speculated, if one were really being deceived by a perfect robot-simulation of a human, the phenomenon of the uncanny valley would disappear. That phenomenon requires that one be at least minimally cognizant of one's experience as the experience of a simulation. The resulting aversion to the too-close approximation of reality, I argued, was an aversion to being deceived. So, on my account anyway, the really interesting question is not whether reality can be perfectly simulated or not, but whether or not we could ever have the experience of a perfect simulation qua simulation. So, here's a claim that I want to add to my earlier musings on the uncanny valley:

Any possibility for an account of the "perfect simulation" requires, necessarily, a third.

The person experiencing a perfect simulation, if it is indeed "perfect," does not experience it as a "simulation," and consequently will have no conceptual or linguistic tools at his or her disposal for giving an account of it as a "perfect simulation." (This is, of course, the age-old Cartesian worry, played out ad nauseum in brain-in-a-vat thought experiments and The Matrix movies.) I'm not sure that the recent neuroscientific experiments on mirror neurons or the psycho-physiology of empathy really disrupts this claim, given that even those experiments recognize that the first-person experience of pain or joy is categorically different from the empathetic experience of the same. In order for a simulation to be a simulation, it must be recognizably distinct from that which it is simulating. (Otherwise, it would just be "real," right?) So, if there is to be any account of a "perfect simulation"-- again, qua simulation-- it requires that there be an observer, independent from the person experiencing the simulation, who can still experience, understand, and articulate the difference between the simulation and reality. (Someone like the "Morpheus" character in The Matrix... or someone like the observing scientist in the laboratory full of brains-in-vats.) But, of course, if the observer-- who still realizes the "perfect" simulation as a simulation-- is the only one who can give an account of it, then... alas, we still do not really have an account of the "experience" of the perfect simulation. We have an account of the experience of "the experience of the perfect simulation." Why? Because, again, we need the ability to distinguish between a thing and its opposite, the basic law of noncontradiction, in order to give a sensible account of anything we experience.

The person experiencing the perfect simulation no longer has that ability. What that person has is, in "reality," the coincidental experience of A (a real thing) and not-A (a simulation of a real thing, that is, an unreal thing)... only that is a thoroughly irrational experience, both unthinkable and unsayable.

[Why, you may be asking, does this require a "third"? Why not simply a "second"? Well, I formulate it that way because I'm trying to stay within the parameters of the uncanny valley theory, which is not about any-old simulated experience, but the simulation of an experience between two human beings, or a human being and a very-human-like robot. So, in that scenario, I think we need three: the primary subject, the "other" whom he or she is experiencing (which may or may not be a simulated human being), and the "third" observer.]

One last thing, which may or may not make this clearer. (And which, not unrelatedly, hearkens back to a an essay I wrote a long time ago entitled Anatomy of an Illusion, inspired by Christopher Nolan's film The Prestige.) I think the difference between the experience of a perfect simulation, on the one hand, and the experience of the experience of a perfect simulation, on the other hand, highlights something structurally similar to the difference between the experience of "magic" (with an understanding here that "magic" is really illusion and trickery) and the experience of a "miracle." A perfect magic trick aims to entirely veil the part of it that is a "trick," to produce the illusion of not being an illusion, and thus to make its appearance in our experience appear as a miracle. (Material objects don't just disappear and reappear with an 'abracadabra' and a wave of a wand! You can't saw a woman in half and then put her back together! Natural laws cannot be suspended! It must be a miracle!) If we ever really had the experience of a perfect magic trick, one that perfectly masked its illusion, we would, in effect, have the experience of a miracle. But, in fact, when we watch a magician do his trick, even if he is very, very good at it, we are experiencing it as an illusion, as a trick, as a simulation of something miraculous. That is why we can give an account of our experience of it as magic, and not miracle. Compare that to the experience of watching a young child in his or her first encounter with a really good magician. The child experiences the trick as real; in fact, the child does not experience it as a "trick." We adults, looking on and knowing that there is no such thing as "real" magic, can observe the total assimilation of reality and illusion that the child is experiencing, but neither we nor the child are in fact having the experience of a "perfect illusion."

It's either an illusion, in which case it is not perfect, or it's perfect, in which case it is no longer an illusion. In the parlance of The Matrix, you either take the blue pill or the red pill. The consequent implications of that choice in your experience are mutually exclusive. That's why there's no uncanny valley in the perfect simulation and, further, why there may be no "experience" of the perfect simulation at all.